Theosophy Home Our Facebook Group |
CONTENTS |
||
Annie Besant
[Page 1] MEMORY is but a function of the
mind, and the answer given to the question, 'What is memory?' must turn on
the answer given to the larger question, 'What is mind?' 'Is there a Self or
Ego, of which mind, as we know it, is a part; or is mind only the outcome of
matter in motion, so that the Self has no real existence? Is mind anything
more than an ever changing succession of perceptions and congeries of
perceptions, and these the outcome of nervous activity responding to
stimuli, peripheral and central? Or is it a definite mode of being, with
perceptions et hoc genus omne as material on which it works; with
faculties whereby it perceives, reproduces, recollects, conceives; but no
more as a whole to be identified with its functional activities than the
body as a whole consists of eating, breathing or digesting?'
The famous argument of Hume, in the fifth and sixth sections of
[Page 2] A Treatise on Human
Nature, part IV, will be familiar to the student; but I
may here recall the results of his introspection:
“For my part, when I enter most intimately into what I call
myself, I always stumble on some particular perception or other, of heat or
cold, light or shade, pain or pleasure. I never can catch myself at
any time without a perception. When my perceptions are removed for any time,
as by sound sleep, so long am I insensible of myself, and may truly
be said not to exist. And were all my perceptions removed by death, and I
could neither think nor feel, nor see, nor live, nor hate, after the
dissolution of my body, I should be entirely annihilated nor can I conceive
what is further necessary to make me a perfect non-entity. If anyone, upon
superior and unprejudiced reflection, thinks he has a different notion of
himself, I must confess I can reason no longer with him. All I can
allow him is, that he may be in the right as well as I, and that we are
essentially different in this particular. He may, perhaps, perceive
something simple and continued which he calls
himself; though I am certain [Page 3]
there is no such principle in me. But, setting aside some metaphysicians of
this kind, I may venture to affirm of the rest of mankind, that they are
nothing but a bundle or collection of different perceptions, which succeed
each other with inconceivable rapidity, and are in a perpetual flux and
movement'.
Hume consequently denies the existence of the Self, and explains that the
feeling of personal identity arises from the relations between the objects
perceived.
Is Mind a Bundle of Perceptions?
But in
reading the whole argument it is impossible to remain unconscious of the
self-contradictory nature of the expressions used. 'When I enter ... I
always stumble upon some perception. 'What is the 'I' that stumbles on a
perception, and is able to observe and to recognize it? Is it itself a
perception? If so, of what? And can one perception in a 'bundle' perceive other
perceptions in the same bundle, and separating itself from its peers scrutinize
the remainder and recognize them as a bundle? The argument implies something
that observes the perceptions and that assigns to each its rightful name and
place. Despite himself, [Page 4] Hume cannot escape from the
consciousness that he is other than his perceptions, and this universal result
of introspection, the consciousness of the 'I', betrays itself in the very
argument aimed at its annihilation. The mind is no more identifiable with its
organs than is the brain with the body of which it is a part. It depends on them
for its living, and its functioning, but IT IS NOT THEY. Consider an ordinary perception, say the perception of a chair. Can that
perception cognize another, or be anything more than the perception of a chair?
If the mind be only a bundle of perceptions, of what nature is the perception
that can cognize all the rest, can set itself apart from and above all the rest,
and say, ' you are a perception of cold, and you of heat, and you of pain, and
you of pleasure'? This perception of perceptions is not very different from the
Self that is denied. It is the perceiver, not a perception.
Let anyone experiment on himself; let him shut himself up alone, free from
all interruption from without; let him patiently and steadily investigate his
mental processes; he will find that the shifting contents of his [Page
5] consciousness are not he; that he is other than the
feelings, the perceptions, the conceptions that pass before him, that they are
his, not he, and that he can drive them away, can empty his mind of all save
Self-consciousness, can, in the words of Patanjali, become a 'spectator without
a spectacle' . It may be argued that introspection often yields fallacious results, and that
self-observation is the most difficult of all tasks. Granted. So may our senses
mislead us, but they are the only guides to the objective world that we possess.
Our recognition of their fallibility does not lead us to refuse to use them, but
it makes us test their report to the best of our ability, and compare them with
the common sense of our race. And so with the result of our inner senses, we
test them, compare their reports with those of others; and I venture to say that
the common sense [I use the words in the philosophical meaning, the serisus
communis] of mankind reports the existence of the Self, the permanent Ego
amid all the flux of percepts and concepts, and that its existence is as certain
as any existence around us in the Object-world. [Page 6]
Remembering and Forgetting
But we shall
judge erroneously of the Self if we only take into account the everyday mental
processes, and limit its extent to the extent of the normal waking
consciousness. And I know of no study that can throw more light on our true Self
than the study of memory, for its phenomena prove to us that Consciousness is
something far wider than the consciousness of the moment, as energy, in the
physical world, is something more than the forces acting at any given instant of
time. Analogy is often useful as throwing light into obscure places, and analogy
may serve us here. Physicists speak of energy as 'kinetic' and 'potential', the
active and the latent. So consciousness may be active or latent, and the latter
division is, for each individual, the greater of the twain. We 'forget', as the
phrase goes, more than we 'remember'; but the 'forgotten' has not really passed
out of consciousness, though it has become latent, any more than force is absent
from the avalanche hanging quiescent on the side of a mountain. The forgotten
can be recalled to the active consciousness, and may revolutionize a life as the
avalanche may be set [Page 7] free and expend its stored-up
energy in laying desolate the valley homes. No force can be annihilated on the
physical plane, and no experience destroyed on the mental. That which the normal
waking consciousness retains depends on the attention, but a name for a phase of
will. That which is best remembered is that which has struck us vividly, i.e.,
that which has arrested and fixed our attention; or that which has been often
repeated so that our attention has been frequently directed to it; in every case
the will lies at the root of the retention. Everything that once enters into
consciousness leaves thereon its trace; the mind is thereby modified, as
Patanjali would phrase it. If this be so the traces should be recoverable, and
on this we must challenge the phenomena of memory.
Let us note, at the commencement, that memory has two chief divisions —
reproduction and recollection. Reproduction may occur without recollection, and
then no recognition will ensue. Memory reproduces the image of a past
perception; it will appear to consciousness as new, unless recollection
[Page 8] accompanies the reproduction, and instances of this are on
record.
'Maury relates that he once wrote an article on political economy for a
periodical, but the sheets were mislaid and, therefore, not sent off. He had
already forgotten everything that he had written when he was requested to send
the promised article. On re-undertaking the work, he thought he had found a
completely new point of view for the subject; but when, some months later, the
missing sheets were found, it appeared, not only that there was nothing new in
his second essay, but that he had repeated his first ideas in almost exactly the
same words.' [Maury, Le Sommeil et les Rêves, p 440
quoted by du Prel, Philosophy of Mysticism, English Translation. vol 2,
p 13, trans from German by C C Massey, London 1889] Leibnitz is
quoted by du Prel as giving an analogous instance: 'I believe that dreams often
renew old thoughts. When Julius Scaliger had celebrated in verse all the famous
men of Verona, there appeared to him in a dream one who gave the name of
Brugnolus, a Bavarian by birth, who had settled at Verona, complaining that he
had been forgotten. Julius Scaliger did not [Page 9] recollect
to have heard him spoken of, but upon this dream made elegiac verses in his
honour. Afterwards his son, Joseph Scaliger, being on a journey through Italy,
learned that formerly there had been at Verona a celebrated grammarian or critic
of that name, who had contributed to the restoration of learning in Italy'.
[ Ibid pp 14 -15 ] The explanation suggested by
Leibnitz is that Scaliger had heard of Brugnolus, but had forgotten him; in the
dream, reproduction took place but was not accompanied by recollection, so that
the name and character appeared new to Scaliger, and he failed to recognize the
dream-presented image. It is impossible to say how much of our dreams may be of
this character, and how often the absence of recognition may bestow on them the
appearance of revelation. We find ourselves in some place that we have dreamed
of, and recognize as real our dream surroundings. Searching our waking
consciousness in vain for some record, we rashly conclude that the dream has
depicted in some mysterious way an environment unknown to us; whereas it is far
more [Page 10] probable that memory has reproduced in our
sleeping consciousness the images of perceptions long since forgotten, and
recollection failing, they pass before the mind as new.
Flashbacks before
Death
To return to the statement that 'everything that
has once entered consciousness leaves thereon its trace'. In the section on
'Memory of the Dying', [Page 69 et seq.] some examples are given of the
remarkable reproduction, at the end of life, of events and surroundings of
childhood, and almost everyone must have come across instances of aged persons
who recall with extreme vividness the trivial occurrences of their youth. Dr
Winslow
[Diseases of the Brain and Mind, pages 286-287
]
remarks on some instances in which, 'in very advanced life the faculty of
memory exhibits an extraordinary degree of elasticity and a surprising amount of
vigour. ... A charming illustration of this fact occurs in the life of Niebuhr,
the celebrated Danish traveller. When old, blind, and so infirm that he was able
only to be carried from his bed to his chair, he used to describe to his friends
the scenes which he had visited in [Page 11] his early days
with wonderful minuteness and vivacity. When they expressed their astonishment
at the vividness of his memory, he explained 'that as he lay in bed, all visible
objects shut out, the pictures of what he had seen in the East continually
floated before his mind's eye, so that it was no wonder that he could speak of
them as if he had seen them yesterday. With like vividness the deep intense sky
of Asia, with its brilliant and twinkling hosts of stars, on which he had so
often gazed by night, or its lofty vault of blue by day, was reflected in the
hours of stillness and darkness on his inmost soul'.
Yet more remarkable as a proof that that which has passed out of ordinary
consciousness is not destroyed, are the many cases on record describing the
strange revival of memory, just ere consciousness becomes latent, which is one
of the most marked phenomena of drowning. I select the following from Du Prel:
[ Op cit vol I, pp 92-93]
At the approach of death, also, the extraordinary exaltation of memory,
connected with a change in the measure of time, has [Page 12]
been frequently observed. Fechner
[Zentralblatt für Anthropologie und Natur
wissenschaft, Jahargang
The approach of death, like extreme old age, will sometimes revive in the
memory the impressions of childhood to the obliteration of more recent habits.
Dr Winslow [ Loc.cit., P.320] quotes Dr Rush
as recording a statement of the [Page 14]
Rev. Dr Muhlenberg, of Lancaster, USA, who 'alluding to the German emigrants
over whom he exercised pastoral care, observes, 'people generally pray shortly
before death in their native language. This is a fact that I have found true in
innumerable cases among my German hearers, although hardly one word of their
native language was spoken by them in common life and when in health'.
Memory
Stimulated by Disease
Passing attacks of disease will alter the contents
of memory in the most remarkable way, so that the view seems wellnigh forced
upon us that the consciousness retains all impressions, but that the
threshold below which all is latent, shifts, as it were, up and down, now
letting some images appear in the active consciousness and now others. The
following three illustrative cases are from Dr Winslow's work. [Op.
cit. pp 320-321] 'Dr Hutchinson refers to the case of a
physician who had in early life renounced the principles of the Roman Catholic
Church. During an attack of delirium which preceded his death he prayed only in
the forms of the Church of Rome, while all recollection of the prescribed
[Page 15] formulae of the Protestant religion was effaced and
obliterated from the mind by the cerebral infection. A gentleman was thrown from
his horse while hunting. He was taken from the field to a neighbouring cottage
in a state of unconsciousness, and was subsequently removed to his own
residence. For the period of a week his life was considered in imminent danger.
When he was sufficiently restored to enable him to articulate, he began to talk
German, a language he had acquired in early life, but had not spoken for nearly
twenty-five years . . . A gentleman had a serious attack of illness. When
restored, it was found that he had lost all recollection of recent
circumstances, but had a lucid memory as to events that had occurred in
early life, in fact, impressions, that had long been forgotten, were again
revived. As this patient recovered his bodily health, a singular alteration was
observed in the character of his memory. He again recollected recent
ideas, but entirely forgot all the events of past years'..
Another class ot proofs of the permanence of impressions on the consciousness
may be
[Page 16] drawn from the recorded cases of the exaltation of
memory, which frequently accompanies disease and abnormal conditions of the
nervous system. Du Prel has collected a large number of instances, from which I
take the following: [ Loc. cit vol 2, pp 19, 21-28 ]
'Coleridge mentions a maid-servant who, in the delirium of fever, recited long
passages in Hebrew which she did not understand, and could not repeat when in
health, but which formerly, when in the service of a priest, she had heard him
deliver aloud. She also quoted passages from theological works, in Latin and
Greek, which she only half understood, when the priest, as was his custom, read
aloud his favourite authors on going to and from church.
[ Maudsley, Physiology and Pathology of the Soul,
p.14 ]. A Rostock peasant, in a fever, suddenly recited the
Greek words commencing the Gospel of St John, which he had accidentally heard
sixty years before; and Benecke mentions a peasant woman who, in fever, uttered
Syriac, Chaldean and Hebrew words which, when a little girl, she had
accidentally heard in the house of a [Page 17] scholar . . .
[Radestock, Schlaj und Traum, p.136] A deranged
person, who was cured by Dr Willis, said that in his attacks his memory attained
extraordinary power, so that long passages from Latin authors occurred to him .
. . [Reil, Raphsodien p.304] A girl of seven,
employed as neatherd [Cowherd], occupied a room divided only by a thin partition
from that of a violin player, who often gave himself up to his favourite pursuit
during half the night. Some months later, the girl got another place, in which
she had already been for two years, when frequently in the night tones exactly
like those, of the violin were heard coming from her room, but which were
produced by the sleeping girl herself. This often went on for hours, sometimes
with interruptions, after which she would continue the song where she had left
off. With irregular intervals, this lasted for two years. Then she reproduced
also the tones of a piano which was played in the family, and afterwards she
began to speak, and held forth with remarkable acuteness on political and
religious subjects, often in a very accomplished and sarcastic way; she also
conjugated [Page 18] Latin, or spoke like a tutor to a pupil.
In all which cases this entirely ignorant girl merely reproduced what had been
said by members of the family or visitors'.
I have quoted this last case in order to draw attention to the significant
fact that sleep may cause the shifting of the threshold, as well as sickness or
insanity.
Dr Winslow [ loc. cit. pp.336-338 ] gives
some cases of extraordinary memory, characterizing incipient brain-disease, and
he also records many curious instances of double consciousness, in which the
patient practically lives a double life, remembering in each state only those
incidents which occurred in it. [
Pp.332-338] Here, again, we seem to be confronted with the
shifting threshold as the only tenable hypothesis.
Persons under hypnotism frequently exhibit an extreme exaltation of memory,
repeating long passages read to them but once, recalling with accuracy long past
and trivial events, describing minutely the insignificant occurrences of many
successive days. Many [Page 19] instances of this kind will be
found by the student in Binet and Féré's Animal Magnetism, and in Dr
Richer's Études sur la grande Hystérie.
With this rough survey of the field of memory in our minds, we must seek for
some hypothesis which will resume the facts, and which, tested by fresh
experiments, will explain other memory-phenomena. I put Humes hypothesis out of
court, and proceed to consider the materialistic and theosophical theories of
memory, to answer the question whether memory is a function of matter in motion,
or a faculty of the Self functioning through matter, but not resultant
from it.
The Materialistic Theory of Memory
According to this theory, memory, like all other
mental functions, is the result of the vibrations of the brain nerve-cells, and
may be expressed in terms of matter and motion. When a stimulus from the
object-world sets up a vibration in a sense-organ, that vibration is propagated
as a wave from cell to cell [Page 20] of the nervous chain till
it reaches its appropriate center in the cerebrum. There arises the perception,
the outcome of mental
activity. This nervous action, once set up, tends to repeat itself more easily
with each similar stimulus, the nervous energy following the path of least
resistance and each occurrence of the similar vibration making easier further
repetition. Such a vibration having once been set up, it may recur in the
absence of the external stimulus, and we have the idea in lieu of the
sensation-perception. Whenever the nerve cells vibrate as they vibrated under
the first stimulus, the ideas recur, and this recurrence is termed memory. Now,
when the vibration is first set up, it is at its strongest, and it is argued
that this intensity of vibration lessens until it is not sufficient to affect
the consciousness. Mr James Ward writes: [Journal and
Speculative Philosophy, vol xvii no 2 quoted by Sully, Outlines of
Psychology.]
'What now do we know of this central image in the intervals when it is not
consciously presented? Manifestly our knowledge in this case can only be
inferential at the best. But there are two facts, the importance of which
[Page 21] Herbart was the first to see, from which we may learn
something. I refer to what he calls the rising and falling of presentations. All
presentations having more than a limited intensity rise gradually to a maximum
and gradually decline: and when they have fallen below the threshold of
consciousness altogether, the process seems to continue; for the longer the time
that elapses before their 'revival', the fainter they appear when revived, and
the more slowly they rise. This evanescence is more rapid at first, becoming
less as the intensity of the presentation diminishes. It is too much to say that
this holds with mathematical accuracy, although Herbart has gone this length.
Still, it is true enough to suggest the notion that an object, even when it is
no longer able to influence attention, continues to be presented, though with
ever less and less absolute intensity, till at length its intensity declines to
an almost dead level just above zero. Put into the materialistic language this
would be that the nervous elements vibrate at first strongly and continue to
vibrate, with less and less vigour, until the vibration is insufficient to
affect the [Page
22] consciousness, and the image sinks below the threshold.
The vibrations go on, still diminishing, but not ceasing; if they cease
the image is lost beyond revival; if they continue, however feebly, they may be
reinforced and once more rise to an intensity which lifts them above the
threshold of consciousness. Such reinforcement is due to association. As Sully
put it very clearly: [Outlines of Psychology, pp
236-237
]
'In order to understand more precisely what is meant by the Law of Contiguous
Association, we may let A and B stand for two impressions [percepts] occurring
together, and a and
b for the two representations answering to these. Then the Law
asserts that when A [or
a] recurs it will tend to excite or call up b; and similarly
that the recurrence of B [or b] will tend to excite a. . . The
physiological explanation of this association seems to be the fact that two
nerve structures that have repeatedly acted together acquire a disposition to
act in combination in the same way. This fact is explained by the hypothesis
that such a conjoint action of two nerve centers somehow tends to fix the line
of
[Page 23] nervous excitation or nervous discharge when one
center is again stimulated in the direction of the other. In other words, paths
of connection are formed between the two regions. But it may be doubted whether
physiologists can as yet give a satisfactory account of the nervous concomitants
of the associative process.
The Physiological Side
Lewes defines memory on the physiological side
as 'an organized tendency to react on lines previously traversed' [The
Physical Basis of Mind ]; and Herbert Spencer relates
each class of feelings to its own group of cells [vesicles] in the brain. He
says:
'f the association of each feeling with its general class answers to the
localisation of the corresponding nervous action within the great nervous
mass in which all feelings of that class arise' if the association of this
feeling with its sub-class answers to the localisation of the nervous action
within that part of this great nervous mass in which feelings of this
sub-class arise, and so on to the end with the smallest groups of feelings
and smallest clusters of nerve-vesicles; then, to [Page 24]
what answers the association of each feeling with predecessors identical in
kind? It answers to the re-excitation of the particular vesicle or vesicles
which, when before excited, yielded the like feeling before experienced; the
appropriate stimulus having set up in certain vesicles the molecular changes
which they undergo when disturbed, there is aroused a feeling of the same
quality with feelings previously aroused when such stimuli set up such
changes in these vesicles. And the association of feeling with the preceding
like feelings corresponds to the physical re-excitation of the same
structures'.
[The Principles of Psychology. London 1831 vol I,
p 258]
We are then to regard memory as the result of the re-excitation of vesicles
of the brain the theory is clear and definite enough. Is it true?
The first difficulty that arises is the limited space available for the
containment of these vesicles, and the consequent limitation of their
number. It is true that their possible combinations may be practically
infinite in number, but this does not help us; for they are to continually
vibrate, however feebly, so long [Page 25] as an idea is
capable of revival, and a vesicle vibrating simultaneously in some thousands
of combinations would be in a parlous molecular condition. For all these
combinations must exist simultaneously, and each must maintain its
inter-related vibrations without cessation. Now, is this possible? It is
true that from the vibrating strings of a piano you may get myriads of
combinations of notes; but you cannot have all these combinations sounding
from the strings at the same time, some loud and some soft, some forcible
and some feeble. By keeping the loud pedal down you may keep some
combinations going for a short time, while you produce fresh vibrations; but
what is the effect? A blurred confusion of sounds, causing an intolerable
discord. If we are to explain memory under the laws of matter in motion, we
must accept the consequences deducible from these laws, and these
consequences are inconsistent with the facts of memory as we know them. Any
attempt to represent clearly in consciousness the physical concomitants of
memory as merely the outcome of vibrating nervous elements will prove to the
student the impossibility of the [Page 26] hypothesis. The
brain is a sufficiently wonderful mechanism as the organ of mind; as the
creator of mind it is inconceivable.
Du Prel [Philosophy of Mysticism, vol 2, pp
108-109]
helps us to realize the difficulties enveloping the materialistic
hypothesis. On this hypothesis 'Memory' would depend on material
brain-traces, left behind by impressions; by the act of memory such traces
are continually renewed, rechiselled as it were, and so there arise
well-worn tracks [Herbert Spencer's 'lines of least resistance'], 'in which
the coach of memory is conducted with especial facility'. And he adds:
'The deductions from this view had already been drawn by the materialists of
the last century. Hook and others recognized that, since one-third of a
second sufficed for the production of an impression, in one hundred years a
man must have collected in his brain 9,467,180,000 traces or copies of
impressions, or, reduced by one-third for the period of sleep,
3,155,760,000; thus in fifty years, 1,577,880,000; further that, allowing a
weight of four pounds to the brain, and subtracting one pound for blood and
vessels and another for [Page 27] the external integument,
a single grain of brain substance must contain 205,542 traces.. . .
Moreover, our intellectual life does not consist in mere impressions; these
form only the material of our judgment. These brain-atoms do not help us to
judgment, notwithstanding their magical properties, so that we must suppose
that whenever we form a sentence or a judgment the impressions are combined,
like the letters in a compositor's box, these atoms however, being at the
same time compositor and box'.
There is another result that would follow from memory being only the outcome
of vibrating cells, and I may be permitted to quote it from my essay on
hypnotism: 'Memory is the faculty which receives the impressions of our
experiences and preserves them; many of these impressions fade away, and we
say we have forgotten. Yet it is clear that these impressions may be
revived. They are, therefore, not destroyed, but are so faint that they sink
below the threshold of consciousness, and so no longer form part of its
normal content. If thought be but a 'mode of motion', memory must be
similarly regarded; [Page 28] but it is not possible to
conceive that each impression of our past life, recorded in consciousness,
is still vibrating in the same group of cells, only so feebly that it does
not rise over the threshold. For these same cells are continually being
thrown into groupings for new vibrations, and these cannot all co-exist, and
the fainter ones be each capable of receiving fresh impulse which may so
intensify their motion as to raise them again into consciousness. Now if
these vibrations = Memory, if we have only matter in motion, we know the
laws of dynamics sufficiently well to say that if a body be set vibrating,
and new forces be successively brought to act on it and set up new
vibrations, there will not be in that body the co-existence of each separate
set of vibrations successively impressed upon it, but it will vibrate in a
way differing from each single set and compounded of all. So that memory as
a mode of motion, would not give us the record of the past, but would
present us with a new story, the resultant of all those past vibrations, and
this would be ever changing as new impressions, causing new vibrations, come
[Page 29] in to modify the resultant of the whole'. If the reader
have in mind the phenomena of memory given in the earlier part of this
essay; if he note that these seem to imply that we forget nothing,
i.e., that every vibration caused throughout the life persists; if,
remembering this, he once more attempts to represent clearly in
consciousness the brain-condition required by this theory, is it too much to
say that he will be compelled to admit that it is inconceivable?
Nor can we forget that there is a certain race-memory, wrought into our
physical organisms, which still further complicates the work to be
accomplished by these over-burdened vesicles. This unconscious memory of the
body, derived from physical inheritance, cannot be wholly thrown out of
account when we deal with cell-vibrations.
The Theosophical Theory of Memory
Here I must guard myself. I cannot really put
forward the theosophical theory, for I do not find it set out in any work that I
have read. I can only suggest a theory, which seems to me, [Page 30]
as a student of Theosophy, to be fairly deducible from the constitution of man
as laid down in theosophical treatises. We learn to distinguish between the true
individuality, the Ego, and the temporary personality that clothes it. The Ego
is the conscious, the thinking agent. It is the Ego of whom the mind forms part,
one of whose functions is memory. Every event that occurs passes into the
consciousness of the Ego and is there stored up; the past is thus for it ever
the present, since all is present in consciousness. [All is
present in eternal ideation Alaya, the universal soul and consciousness
- we are taught; and the higher Ego [Manas] is the first-born of
Alaya or Mahat, being called Manasaputra = 'Son of
Mind'.] But how far the Ego can impress its knowledge on the
brain of the physical organism with which it is connected, and thus cause this
knowledge to enter the consciousness of the person concerned, must, in the
nature of the case, depend on the condition of the organism at the moment, and
the laws within which it works. What we call the threshold of consciousness
divides what is 'remembered' from what is 'forgotten'. All above the threshold
is within the personal consciousness, while all [Page 31] below
this threshold is outside it. But this threshold belongs to the personal
consciousness, and 'here is the significant point' varies with the material
conditions of the moment. It is movable, not fixed and the contents of
consciousness vary with the movement of the threshold. Thus:
Let
A B represent the consciousness of the Ego; let C D represent the threshold of
consciousness of the person; of all above C D the person will be conscious, it
will be impressed on the material brain; of all below C D he will be
unconscious. But if C D be movable upwards and downwards, the contents of his
consciousness will vary with its [Page 32] movement, and he
will remember or forget according as the idea is above or below this dividing
line.
[We have to exclude from this the impressions of a purely
physical nature, such as enter in the category of animal perception and
memory. Such impressions reach the human Ego, and it cannot fail to note them;
but they do not impress themselves indelibly on
its consciousness, and can never, therefore, follow the Ego to
Devachan.]
Waking and
Dreaming Consciousness
Now the condition of the organism is constantly
varying; but there are two states of consciousness that occur in everyone and
are, clearly distinguishable 'the waking consciousness and the dream
consciousness. The contents of these differ to a remarkable extent, and they
work under curiously different conditions. The waking consciousness works under
conditions of time and space; the dream consciousness is free from them — it can
live through years in a second of time, it can annihilate space in its
movements. In the dream the place of the dreamer depends on his thought, he is
where he thinks himself. Not only so, but the dream consciousness often retains
events erased from the waking memory. Let the reader turn back to pages 8 and 9,
and note the curious phenomena of reproduction without recollection in the dream
[Page 33] state. Is it an impossible theory that when the senses are
closed to the object-world, when the bodily functions have touched their lowest
activity, then the Ego may be able to impress on this negative organism far more
of its own contents than it can impress upon it when in its more vigorous state?
Does it not seem as though that which is below the threshold of the waking
consciousness becomes that which is above the threshold of the dream
consciousness, and as though the double life of waking and sleeping is but the
activity of the one Ego working under the contrasted physical conditions?
If this be not so, we seem to be driven to the conception of a duality at the
very centre of being; each man is not one, but twain, in the innermost recesses
of consciousness.
On the other hand, the theory for which I contend leaves the individuality
single, varying in its manifestations according to the physical conditions
through which it works; and all the strange cases of double consciousness, which
have so perplexed the physiologist and the psychologist, together with the
phenomena of somnambulism, mesmerism, [Page 34] hypnotism, and
similar conditions, fall into line as severally belonging to one of the two
states of consciousness, the dream and the waking, the Ego working equally in
either, but conditioned in turn by each.
'Ordinary sleep' as du Prel says, 'is a condition intermediate between waking
and somnambulism, the latter being only its exaltation'. In this connection
these facts are to be noted; if we sleep lightly and dream, we remember our
dreams; if we sleep more soundly, we sometimes remember the dream more vividly
on waking, but in an hour or two we have completely forgotten it and cannot
revive the memory, try as we may; in deep sleep we dream, as has often been
discovered by closely watching a person wrapped in profound slumber, but no
trace remains on our waking memory. In somnambulism, which is closely allied to
this deep sleep, no memory persists, as a rule, into a waking state. A person
who is a somnambulist lives a double life; sleeping, he remembers his sleep
experiences and sometimes his waking ones; waking he remembers only his waking
life. Occasionally, but only [Page 35] rarely, the golden
bridge of memory spans the gulf between the waking and the somnambulic
consciousness, dreams sometimes interposing as connecting link between the two.
It must be remembered that a somnambulist, left to himself, will pass into
ordinary sleep before awaking, and when this is the case dream may carry on
memory of the somnambulist into the waking state.
Transcendental
Consciousness
Du Prel
puts very clearly the existence of what he calls the 'transcendental
consciousness', which has much in common, though it is not identical with,
the theosophical Ego:
'There can be no right theory of remembering without the right theory of
forgetting. The phenomenon of alternating consciousness shows that very
clearly. It is only when we know what becomes of an impression which is
forgotten, that we can answer the question whence it comes to memory. Now,
what is the process of forgetting? It is a disappearance from the normal
sense consciousness. There can be no destruction of the impression, or its
reproduction would be impossible. Excluding the brain-trace theory, there
must be a psychical organ, preserving [Page 36] the
faculty of reproduction, even if the impression, as product of its
earlier activity, should be destroyed. This organ, lying beyond the
self-consciousness, belongs to the unconscious. If, however, this organ had
simply the latent faculty of reproduction, and did not rather draw into
itself and preserve unchanged the impression as product, we should have
again within this organ to distinguish between the conscious and the
unconscious. The hypothesis would thus explain nothing, the difficulty being
merely pushed back and transposed. There is therefore, no alternative but to
say that this organ is not in itself at all unconscious, but only so from
the standpoint of the sense-consciousness; that it is not merely a latent
faculty of reproduction but takes up into its consciousness the
impression, as the latter disappears from the external consciousness. By
this admission of a transcendental consciousness, the possibility of memory
is explained by the mere transposition of the psycho-physical threshold with
every retreat of the boundary between the sense and the transcendental
consciousness. If a forgotten impression sank [Page 37]
into a real unconscious, it would not be apparent how in memory this
unconscious should suddenly become again conscious. The forgotten,
therefore, cannot thereby cease to belong to a consciousness, and since
forgetting is the disappearance from the sense-consciousness, we must admit
the existence of a second. And so, to say that an impression is forgotten
means that it has passed over from the sense-consciousness to the
transcendental. [Op cit vol 2, pp 111 -13].
Hyper-Ethereal
The answer to this that would leap to the lips of
the materialist is that the impression 'goes' nowhere, any more than motion
'goes' anywhere when a wheel is stopped. But this obvious answer leaves out
important facts in the case. The motion is changed into another form of physical
energy, as heat caused by the friction which stops it, and the wheel cannot
reproduce the motion; the new impulse to move must come from a living force
without it. Now the impression is revivable, without any external
action, by Self-action, and the materialist theory of memory implies its
continual production by ceaselessly vibrating vesicles, albeit the [Page
38] vibrations be not vigorous enough to attract attention.
If we admit the existence of the Ego, personal memory would be the power of
the personal brain to receive impressions from it; to respond, so to speak, to
the subtler vibrations of, perhaps, the 'thought-stuff' of which Clifford
dreamed. Comparing the vibrations of our gross forms of matter with the
vibrations of the ether we can reason by analogy to a form of matter as much
subtler than nerve-matter of our brain. There, indeed, may be the possibility of
vibrations such as are necessary to make our thought process conceivable. At
present, this can only be a hypothesis to us, but it is a hypothesis which
throws light on this obscure subject, and may be provisionally accepted, until
further researches prove or disprove it.
Here will find their justification all attempts to refine and increase the
sensitiveness of the nerve-matter of the brain, for increased delicacy will mean
increased faculty of responding to the hyper-ethereal vibrations that is, it
will enable the Ego to impress on our personal consciousness more and more the
[Page 39]
contents of his own. By this theory we can understand the exalted mental
faculties of the somnambulist, the tension of the nervous system rendering it
more sensitive, i.e., more responsive. By it we can understand the
danger of the ignorant striving after this abnormal condition, the nervous
elements becoming exhausted by over-rapid discharge and excessive strain. 'Great
wits to madness often are allied' is only too true; the sensitiveness which is
genius may easily pass into the hyper-sensitiveness that is insanity.
And so we reach the practical conclusion — to walk warily in these
little-trodden realms, because there is a danger; but to walk, because without
courage to face the darkness no light can come. [Page 40]
by Annie Besant
THE nature
of memory is a problem which has been troubling theosophical students for many
years, and perhaps I may also succeed in troubling them still further by
offering a theory on the subject; on the other hand it is possible that I may
succeed in helping them a little by the presentation of a view that is to myself
helpful and clarifying.
What is memory? How does it work? By what means do we recover the past,
whether near or remote? For, after all, whether the past be near or remote,
belonging to this or to any anterior life, the means which govern its recovery
must be similar, and we require a theory which will include all cases of memory,
and at the same time will enable us to understand each particular case.
The first step towards obtaining a definite and intelligible theory is a
comprehension [Page 41] of our own composition, of the Self
with its sheaths, and their inter-relation. We must bear constantly in mind the
facts that our consciousness is a unit, and that this unit of consciousness
works through various sheaths, which impose upon it a false appearance of
multiplicity. The innermost, or most tenuous, of these sheaths is inseparable
from the unit of consciousness; in fact, it is this sheath which makes it a
unit. This unit is the Monad, dwelling on the Anupadaka plane; but for all
practical purposes we may take it as the familiar inner Man, the Tri-Atom,
Atma-Buddhi-Manas, thought of as apart from the Atmic, Buddhic and Manasic
sheaths. This unit of consciousness manifests through, abides in, sheaths
belonging to the five planes of its activity, and we call it the Self working in
its sheaths.
We must think, then, of a conscious Self dwelling in vehicles that vibrate.
The vibrations of these vehicles correspond, on the side of matter, with the
changes in consciousness in the side of the Self. We cannot accurately speak of
vibrations of consciousness, because vibrations can only belong to [Page
42] the material side of things, the form side, and only loosely can we
speak of a vibrating consciousness corresponding with vibrations in sheaths.
The question of the vehicles, or bodies, in which consciousness, the Self, is
working, is all-important as regards memory. The whole process of recovering
more or less remote events is a question of picturing them in the sheath 'of
shaping part of the matter of the sheath into their likeness' in which
consciousness is working at the time. In the Self, as a fragment of the
universal Self ' which for our purpose we can take to be the LOGOS, although in
verity the LOGOS is but a portion of the universal Self' is present in
everything; for in the universal Self is present all which has taken place, is
taking place, and will take place in the universe; all this, and an illimitable
more is present in the universal Consciousness. Let us think only of a universe
and its LOGOS. We speak of Him as omnipresent and omniscient. Now,
fundamentally, that omnipresence and omniscience are in the individualized Self,
as being one [Page 43] with the LOGOS, but 'we must put in here
a but' with a difference; the difference consisting in this, that while in the
separated Self, as Self, apart from all vehicles, that omnipresence and
omniscience reside by virtue of his unity with the one Self, the vehicles in
which he dwells have not yet learned to vibrate in answer to his change of
consciousness, as he turns his attention to one or another part of his contents.
Hence we say that all exists in him potentially, and not as in the LOGOS
actually: all the changes which go on in the consciousness of the LOGOS are
reproducible in this separated Self, which is an indivisible part of His life,
but the vehicles are not yet ready as media of manifestation. Because of the
separation of form, because of this closing in of the separate, or
individualized, Self, these possibilities which are within it as part of the
Universal Self are latent, not manifest, are possibilities, not
actualities. As in every atom which goes to the making up of a vehicle, there
are illimitable possibilities of vibration, so in every separated Self there are
illimitable possibilities of changes of consciousness. [Page 44]
Self is One with Logos
We do not find in the atom, at the beginning of a
solar system, an illimitable variety of vibrations; but we learn that it
possesses a capacity to acquire an illimitable variety of vibrations; it
acquires these in the course of its evolution, as it responds continually to
vibrations playing upon its surface; at the end of a solar system, an immense
number of the atoms in it have reached the stage of evolution in which they can
vibrate in answer to any vibration touching them that arises within the system;
then, for that system, these atoms are said to be perfected. The same thing is
true for the separated, or individualized, Selves. All the changes taking place
in the consciousness of the LOGOS which are represented in that universe, and
take shape as forms in that universe, all these are also within the perfected
consciousness in that universe, and any of these changes can be reproduced in
any one of them. Here is memory: the re-appearance, the re-incarnation in
matter, of anything that has been within that universe, and therefore ever is,
in the consciousness of its LOGOS, and in the consciousness which are part of
[Page 45] His consciousness. Although we think of the Self as separate
as regards all other Selves, we must ever remember it is in-separate as regards
the ONE SELF, the LOGOS. His life is not shut out from any part of His universe,
and in Him we live and move and have our being, open ever to Him, filled with
His life.
As the Self puts on vehicle after vehicle of matter, its powers of gaining
knowledge become, with each additional vehicle, more circumscribed but also more
definite. Arrived on the physical plane, consciousness is narrowed down to the
experiences which can be received through the physical body, and chiefly through
those openings which we call the sense-organs; these are avenues through which
knowledge can reach the imprisoned Self, though we often speak of them as
shutting out knowledge when we think of the capacities of the subtler vehicles.
The physical body renders perception definitive and clear much as a screen with
a minute hole in it allows a picture of the outside world to appear on a screen
that would otherwise show a blank surface; rays of light are truly shut off from
[Page 46] the screen, but by that very shutting off, those allowed to
enter form a clearly defined picture.
Let us now see what happens as regards the physical vehicle in the reception
of an impression and in the subsequent recall of that impression, i.e.,
in the memory of it.
A vibration from outside strikes on an organ of sense, and is transmitted to
the appropriate centre in the brain. A group of cells in the brain vibrates, and
that vibration leaves the cells in a state somewhat different from the one in
which they were previous to its reception. The trace of that response is a
possibility for the group of cells; it has once vibrated in a particular way,
and it retains for the rest of its existence as a group of cells the possibility
of again vibrating in that same way without again receiving a stimulus from the
outside world. Each repetition of an identical vibration strengthens this
possibility, each leaving its own trace, but many such repetitions will be
required to establish a self-initiated repetition: the cells come nearer to this
possibility of a self-initiated vibration by each repetition compelled from
outside. But this vibration has not stopped with the [Page 47]
physical cells; it has been transmitted inwards to the corresponding cell, or
group of cells, in the subtler vehicles, and has ultimately produced a change in
consciousness. This change, in its turn, re-acts on the cells, and a repetition
of the vibrations is initiated from within by the change in consciousness, and
this repetition is a memory of the object which started the series of
vibrations. The response of the cells to the vibration from outside, a response
compelled by the laws of the physical universe, gives to the cells the power of
responding to a similar impulse, though feebler, coming from within. A little
power is exhausted in each moving of matter in a new vehicle, and hence a
gradual diminution of the energy in the vibration. Less and less is exhausted as
the cells repeat similar vibrations in response to new impacts from without, the
cells answering more readily with each repetition.
Therein lies the value of the 'without'. It wakes up in the matter, more
easily than by any other way, the possibility of response, being more closely
akin to the vehicles than the 'within'.
[Page 48]
The change caused in consciousness, also, leaves the consciousness more ready
to repeat that change than it was at first to yield to it, and each such change
brings the consciousness nearer to the power to initiate a similar change.
Looking back into the dawnings of consciousness, we see that the imprisoned
Selves go through innumerable experiences before a Self-initiated change in
consciousness occurs; but bearing this in mind, as a fact, we can leave these
early stages, and study the workings of consciousness at a more advanced point.
We must also remember that every impact, reaching the innermost sheath and
giving rise to a change in consciousness, is followed by a reaction, the change
in consciousness causing a new series of vibrations from within outwards; there
is the going inwards to the Self, followed by the rippling outwards from the
Self, the first due to the object, and giving rise to what we call a perception,
and the second due to the reaction of the Self, causing what we call a memory.
Memories of Past Lives
A number of sense-impressions, coming through
sight, hearing, touch, taste and smell, [Page 49] run up from
the physical vehicle through the astral to the mental. There they are co-ordinated
into a complex unity, as a musical chord is composed of many notes. This is the
special work of the mental body: it receives many streams and synthesizes them
into one; it builds many impressions into a perception, a thought, a complex
unity.
Let us try to catch this complex thing after it has gone inwards and has
caused a change in consciousness, an idea; the change it has caused gives rise
to new vibrations in the vehicles, reproducing those it had caused on its inward
way, and in each vehicle it reappears in a fainter form. It is not strong,
vigorous and vivid, as when its component parts flashed from the physical to the
astral, and from the astral to the mental; it reappears in the mental in a
fainter form, the copy of that which the mental sent inward, but the vibrations
feebler; as the Self receives from it a reaction — for the impact of a vibration
on touching each vehicle must cause a re-action — that re-action is far
feebler than the original action, and will therefore seem less 'real' than that
action; it makes a lesser [Page 50] change in consciousness,
and that lessening represents inevitably a less 'reality'
So long as the consciousness is too little responsive to be aware of any
impacts that do not come through with the impulsive vigour of the physical, it
is literally more in touch with the physical than with any other sheath, and
there will be no memories of ideas, but only memories of perceptions, i.e.,
of pictures of outside objects, caused by vibrations of the nervous matter of
the brain, reproducing themselves in the related astral and mental matter. These
are literally pictures in the mental matter, as are the pictures on the retina
of the eye. And the consciousness perceives these pictures, 'sees' them, as we
may truly say, since the seeing of the eye is only a limited expression of its
perceptive power. As the consciousness draws a little away from the physical,
turning attention more to the modification in its inner sheaths, it sees these
pictures reproduced in the brain from the astral sheath by its own re-action
passing outwards, and there is the memory of sensations. The picture arises in
the brain by the re-action of the change in consciousness, [Page 51]
and is recognized there. This recognition implies that the consciousness has
withdrawn largely from the physical to the astral vehicle, and is working
therein. The human consciousness is thus working at the present time, and is,
therefore full of memories, these memories being reproductions in the physical
brain of past pictures, caused by re-actions from consciousness. In a lowly
evolved human type, these pictures are pictures of past events in which the
physical body was concerned, memories of hunger and thirst and of their
gratification, of sexual pleasures, and so on, things in which the physical body
took an active part. In a higher type, in which the consciousness is working
more in the mental vehicle, the pictures in the astral body will draw more of
its attention; these pictures are shaped in the astral body by the vibrations
coming outwards from the mental, and are perceived as pictures by the
consciousness as it withdraws itself more into the mental body as its immediate
vehicle. As this process goes on, and the more awakened consciousness responds
to vibrations initiated from outside on the astral plane by astral objects,
these [Page 52] objects grow 'real' and become distinguishable
from the memories, the pictures in the astral body caused by the re-actions from
consciousness.
Let us note, in passing, that with the memory of an object goes hand in hand a
picture of the renewal of the keener experience of the object by physical
contact, and this we call anticipation; and the more complete the memory of an
event the more complete is this anticipation. So that the memory will sometimes
even cause in the physical body the re-actions which normally accompany the
contact with the external object, and we may savor in anticipation pleasures
which are not within present reach of the body. Thus the anticipation of savory
food will cause 'the mouth to water' This fact will again appear, when we reach
the completion of our theory of memory.
Now, having noted the changes in the vehicles which arise from impacts from
the external world, the response to these as changes of consciousness, the
feebler vibrations produced in the vehicles by the re-action of consciousness,
and the recognition of these [Page 53] again by consciousness
as memories, let us come to the crux of the question: What is memory? The
breaking up of the bodies between death and reincarnation puts an end to their
automatism, to their power of responding to vibrations similar to those already
experienced; the responsive groups are disintegrated, and all that remains as a
seed for future responses is stored within the permanent atoms; how feeble this
is, as compared with the new automatisms imposed on the mass of the bodies by
new experiences of the external, may be judged by the absence of any memory of
past lives initiated in the vehicles themselves. In fact, all the permanent
atoms can do is to answer more readily to vibrations of a kind similar to those
previously experienced than to those that come to them for the first time. The
memory of the cells, or of groups of cells, perishes at death, and cannot be
said to be recoverable, as such. Where then is memory preserved?
The brief answer is: memory is not a faculty and is not preserved; it does not
inhere in consciousness as a capacity, nor is any memory of events stored up in
the individual
[Page 54] consciousness. Every event is a present fact in the
universe-consciousness, in the consciousness of the LOGOS; everything that
occurs in His universe, past, present and future, is ever there in His
all-embracing consciousness, in His 'eternal Now'. From the beginning of the
universe to its ending, from its dawn to its sunset, all is there, ever-present,
existent. In that ocean of ideas, all IS; we, wandering in the ocean, touch
fragments of its contents, and our response to the contact is our knowledge;
having known, we can more readily again contact, and this repetition ' when
falling short of the contact of the outside sheath of the moment with the
fragments occupying its own plane' is memory. All 'memories' are recoverable
because all possibilities of image-producing vibrations are within the
consciousness of the LOGOS, and we can share in that consciousness the more
easily as we have previously shared more often similar vibrations; hence, the
vibrations which have formed parts of our experience are more readily repeated
by us than those we have never known, and here comes in the value of the
permanent atoms; the thrill out again, on [Page 55] being
stimulated, the vibrations previously performed, and out of all the
possibilities of vibrations of the atoms and molecules of our bodies those sound
out which answer to the note struck by the permanent atoms. The fact that we
have been affected vibrationally and by changes of consciousness during the
present life makes it easier for us to take out of the universal consciousness
that of which we have already had experience in our own. Whether it be a memory
in the present life, or one in a life long past, the method of recovery is the
same. There is no memory save the ever-present consciousness of the LOGOS, in
whom we literally live and move and have our being; and our memory is merely
putting ourselves into touch with such parts of His consciousness as we have
previously shared.
Hence, according to Pythagoras, all learning is remembrance, for it is the
drawing from the consciousness of the LOGOS into that of the separated Self that
which in our essential unity with Him is eternally ours. On the plane where the
unity overpowers the separateness, we share His consciousness [Page 56]
of our universe; on the lower planes, where the separateness veils the unity, we
are shut out therefrom by our unevolved vehicles. It is the lack of
responsiveness in these which hinders us, for we can only know the planes
through them. Therefore we cannot directly improve our memory; we can only
improve our general receptivity and power to reproduce, by rendering our bodies
more sensitive, while being careful not to go beyond their limit of elasticity.
Also we can 'pay attention'; i.e., we can turn the awareness of
consciousness, we can concentrate consciousness on that special part of the
consciousness of the LOGOS to which we desire to attune ourselves. We need not
thus distress ourselves with calculations as to 'how many angels can stand on
the point of a needle', how we can preserve in a limited space the illimitable
number of vibrations experienced in many lives; for the whole of the
form-producing vibrations in the universe are ever-present, and are available to
be drawn upon by any individual unit, and can be reached as, by evolution, such
a one experiences ever more and more. [Page 57]
Let us apply this to an event in our past life. Some of the circumstances
'remain in our memory', others are 'forgotten'. Really, the event exists with
all its surrounding circumstances, 'remembered' and 'forgotten' alike, in but
one state, the memory of the LOGOS , the universal memory. Anyone who is able to
place himself in touch with that memory can recover the whole circumstances as
much as we can; the events through which we have passed are not ours
but form part of the contents of His consciousness; and our sense of property in
them is only due to the fact that we have previously vibrated to them, and
therefore vibrate again to them more readily than if we contacted them for the
first time.
We may, however, contact them with different sheaths at different times,
living as we do under time and space conditions which vary with each sheath. The
part of the consciousness of the LOGOS that we move through in our physical
bodies is far more restricted than that we move through in our astral and mental
bodies, and the contacts through a well-organized body are far more
[Page 58] vivid than those through a less-organized one.
Moreover, it must be remembered that the restriction of area is due to our
vehicles only; faced by the complete event, physical, astral, mental, spiritual,
our consciousness of it is limited within the range of the vehicles able to
respond to it. We feel ourselves to be among the circumstances which
surround the grossest vehicle we are acting in, and which thus touch it from
'outside'; whereas we 'remember' the circumstances which we contact with the
fine vehicles, these transmitting the vibrations to the grosser vehicle, which
is thus touched from 'within'.
Test of Objectivity
The test of objectivity that we apply to
circumstances 'present' or 'remembered' is that of the 'common sense'. If others
around us see as we see, hear as we hear, we regard the circumstances as
objective; if they do not, if they are unconscious of that of which we are
conscious, we regard the circumstances as subjective. But this test of
objectivity is only valid for those who are active in the same sheaths; if one
person is working in the physical body and another in [Page 59]
the physical and the astral, the things objective to the man in the astral
body cannot affect the man in the physical body, and he will declare them to be
subjective hallucinations. The 'common sense' can only work in similar bodies;
it will give similar results when all are in physical bodies, all in astral, or
all in mental. For the 'common sense' is merely the thought-forms of the LOGOS
on each plane, conditioning each embodied consciousness, and enabling it to
respond by certain changes to certain vibrations in its vehicles. It is by no
means confined to the physical plane, but the average humanity at the present
stage of evolution has not sufficiently unfolded the indwelling consciousness
for them to exercise any 'common sense', on the astral and mental planes.
'Common sense' is an eloquent testimony to the oneness of our indwelling lives:
we see all things around us on the physical plane in the same way, because our
apparently separate consciousnesses are all really part of the one consciousness
ensouling all forms. We all respond in the same general way, according to the
stage of our evolution, because we [Page 60] share the same
consciousness; and we are affected similarly by the same things because the
action and re-action between them and ourselves is the interplay of one life in
varied forms.
Recovery of anything by memory, then, is due to the ever-existence of
everything in the consciousness of the LOGOS, and He has imposed upon us the
limitations of time and space in order that we may, by pratice, be able to
respond swiftly by changes of consciousness to the vibrations caused in our
vehicles by vibrations coming from other vehicles similarly ensouled by
consciousness; thus only can we gradually learn to distinguish precisely and
clearly; contacting things successively — that is, being in time — and
contacting them in relative directions in regard to ourselves and to each other
— that is, being in space — we are gradually unfolded to the state in which we
can recognize all simultaneously and each everywhere — that is, out of time and
space.
As we pass through countless happenings in life we find that we do not keep in
touch with all through which we have passed; [Page 61]
there is a very limited power of response in our physical vehicle, and hence
numerous experiences drop out of its purview. In trance, we can recover these,
and they are said to emerge from the sub-conscious. Truly they remain ever
unchanging in the universal Consciousness, and as we pass by them we become
aware of them, because the very limited light of our consciousness, shrouded in
the physical vehicle, falls upon them, and they disappear as we pass on; but as
the area covered by that same light shining through the astral vehicle is
larger, they again appear when we are in trance — that is in the astral vehicle,
free from the physical; they have not come and gone and come back again, but the
light of our consciousness in the physical vehicle had passed on and so we saw
them not, and the more extended light in the astral vehicle enables us to see
them again. As Bhagavan Das has well said:
'If a spectator wandered unrestingly through the halls of a vast museum, a
great art gallery, at the dead of night, with a single small lamp in one hand,
each of the natural objects, the pictured scenes, the statues, the [Page
62]
portraits, would be illumined by that lamp, in succession, for a single
moment, while all the rest were in darkness, and after that single moment, would
itself fall into darkness again. Let there now be not one but countless such
spectators, as many in endless number as the objects of sight within the place,
each spectator meandering in and out incessantly through the great crowd of all
the others, each lamp bringing momentarily into light one object and for only
that spectator who holds that lamp. This immense and unmoving building is the
rock-bound ideation of the changeless Absolute. Each lamp-carrying spectator out
of the countelss crowd is one line of consciousness out of the pseudo-infinite
lines of such that make up the totality of the one universal consciousness. Each
coming into light of each object is it patency, is an experience of the jiva;
each falling into darkness in its lapse into the latent. From the standpoint of
the objects themselves, or of the universal consciousness, there is no latency,
nor patency. From that of the lines of consciousness, there is'.
[The Science of Peace, second edition, pp.
341-342]
Consciousness ' Turns its Attention'
As vehicle after vehicle comes to fuller working,
the area of light extends, and the consciousness can turn its attention to any
one part of the area and observe closely the objects therein [Page 63]
included. Thus, when the consciousness can function freely on the astral plane,
and is aware of its surroundings there, it can see much that on the physical
plane is 'past' — or 'future', if they be things to which in the 'past' it has
learned to respond. Things outside the area of light coming through the vehicle
of the astral body will be within the area of that which streams from the
subtler mental vehicle. When the causal body is the vehicle, the 'memory of past
lives' is recoverable, the causal body vibrating more readily to events to which
it has before vibrated, and the light shining through it embracing a far larger
area and illuminating scenes long 'past' — those scenes being really no more
past than the scenes of the present, but occupying a different spot in time and
space. The lower vehicles, which have not previously vibrated to these events,
cannot readily directly contact them and answer to them; that belongs to the
causal [Page 64] body, the relatively permanent vehicle. But
when this body answers to them, the vibrations from it readily run downwards,
and may be reproduced in the mental, astral and physical bodies.
The phrase is used above, as to consciousness, that 'it can turn its attention
to any one part of the area, and observe closely the objects therein included'.
This 'turning of the attention' corresponds very closely in consciousness to
what we should call focusing the eye in the physical body. If we watch the
action taking place in the muscles of the eye when we look first at a near and
then at a distant object, or vice versa, we shall be conscious of a slight
movement, and this constriction or relaxation causes a slight compression or the
reverse in the lenses of the eye. It is an automatic action now, quite
instinctive, but it has only become so by practice; a baby does not focus his
eye, nor judge distance. He grasps as readily at a candle on the other side of
the room as at one within his reach, and only slowly learns to know what is
beyond his reach. The effort to see clearly [Page 65] leads to
the focusing of the eye, and presently it becomes automatic. The objects for
which the eye is focused are within the field of clear vision, and the rest are
vaguely seen. So, also, the consciousness is clearly aware of that to which its
attention is turned; other things remain vague, 'out of focus'.
A man gradually learns thus to turn his attention to things long past, as we
measure time. The causal body is put into touch with them, and the vibrations
are then transmitted to the lower bodies. The presence of a more advanced
student will help a less advanced, because when the astral body of the former
has been made to vibrate responsively to long past events, thus creating an
astral picture of them, the astral body of the younger student can more readily
reproduce these vibrations and thus also 'see'. But even when a man has learned
to put himself into touch with his past, and through, his own with that of
others connected with it, he will find it more difficult to turn his attention
effectively to scenes with which he has had no connection; and when that is
mastered, he will still find it difficult [Page 66]
to put himself into touch with scenes outside the experiences of his recent
past; for instance, if he wishes to visit the moon, and by his accustomed
methods launches himself in that direction, he will find himself bombarded by a
hail of unaccustomed vibrations to which he cannot respond, and will need to
fall back on his inherent divine power to answer to anything which can affect
his vehicles. If he seeks to go yet further, to another planetary chain, he will
find a barrier he cannot overleap, the Ring Pass-not of his own planetary Logos.
We thus begin to understand what is meant by the statements that people at a
certain grade of evolution can reach this or that part of the cosmos; they can
put themselves into touch with the consciousness of the LOGOS outside the
limitations imposed by their material vehicles on the less evolved. These
vehicles, being composed of matter modified by the action of the planetary Logos
of the chain to which they belong, cannot respond to the vibrations of matter
differently modified; and the student must be able to use his Atmic body before
he can contact the
[Page 67] universal memory beyond the limits of his own
chain.
Such is the theory of memory which I present for the consideration of
theosophcal students. It applies equally to the small memories and forgettings
of everyday life as to the vast reaches alluded to in the above paragraphs. For
there is nothing small or great to the LOGOS, and when we are performing the
smallest act of memory, we are as much putting ourselves into touch with the
omnipresence and omniscience of the LOGOS, as when we are recalling a far-off
past. There is no 'far- off, and no 'near'. All are equally present at all times
and in all spaces; the difficulty is with our vehicles, and not with that
all-embracing changeless life. All becomes more and more intelligible and more
peace-giving as we think of that Consciousness, in which is no 'before' and no
'after', no 'past' and no 'future'. We begin to feel that these things are but
the illusion, the limitations, imposed upon us by our own sheaths, necessary
until our powers are evolved and at our service. We live unconsciously in this
mighty Consciousness in [Page 68]
which everything is eternally present, and we dimly feel that if we could live
consciously in that Eternal there were peace. I know of nothing that can more
give to the events of life their true proportion than this idea of a
Consciousness in which everything is present from the beginning, in which indeed
there is no beginning and no ending. We learn that there is nothing terrible and
nothing which is more than relatively sorrowful; and in that lesson is the
beginning of a true peace, which in due course shall brighten into joy.
---------------
Copyright © 2016 by Anand Gholap. All rights reserved. Terms of Use of this web-site